'Beyond Identities: The Limits of an Antidiscrimination Approach to Equality' by Martha Fineman in (2012) 92(6)
Boston University Law Review 1713-1770
compares
the legal culture of equality in the United States with the legal cultures of other constitutional democracies. It looks at two manifestations of equality: equality in its narrow sense – as a nondiscrimination mandate – and equality in its broader, substantive sense – as establishing a positive right to access the social goods or resources necessary to sustain equally valued individuals. The article ultimately argues that the foundational difference between the manner in which equality is understood in the United States and how it is understood in much of the rest of the world arises from the recognition and acceptance in other countries that human need and vulnerability are not only an individual responsibility but also a state responsibility.
The U.S. Constitution is ancient by international standards, and it embodies and idealizes an antiquated political-legal subject and a restricted sense of state responsibility that is unrealistic for defining the appropriate legal relationships that exist between the modern state, the lives of individuals, and the operation of complex societal institutions. Clinging to the idea of a “liberal” constitutional or political legal subject that was prevalent when the U.S. Constitution was drafted has impeded the evolution of a concept of equality that would complement our developing understanding of what is necessary in terms of state responsibility to ensure that all people are treated as “created equal.” This article concludes by offering the concept of the “vulnerable subject” as a more viable and appropriate figure around which to build contemporary policy and law and suggesting some measures legislatures and courts could take to build a more responsive and responsible state that would function to ensure meaningful equality of access and opportunity.
In discussing the responsive (and responsible) state Fineman comments that
Powerful, resource-giving institutions like the family, corporations, schools, and financial institutions are both constructs of the state – brought into existence and maintained under the legitimating authority of law and the regulatory machinery of the state – and also the way in which the state constitutes itself. It is the legitimating authority of law and the regulatory machinery of the state that give content and consequences to these institutions and in doing so, illustrate the state’s established monopoly over legitimate means of coercion.
Any contemporary call for a more responsive state must begin with the
observation that the choice is not one between an active state on one hand and
an inactive state on the other. The state is always at least a residual actor.
The choice is one between the state exercising responsibility through the
structuring and regulation of its various institutions or adopting of a policy of
benign neglect and abandonment of responsibility in which its inattentiveness
facilitates and enables patronage, spoilage, and corruption by powerful
individuals and organizations. Insistence that the state be restrained and
government be small, as is prominent in American politics today, ignores the many ways in which the state, through law, shapes and governs institutions from their inception to their dissolution.
The state must also be understood as a political construct as well as a
functioning entity, and as such it expresses certain preferences and values that
should be explored for their accuracy and desirability. Our current conception
of the state as being in need of restraint is built around the privileging of
autonomy in which individuals, institutions, and the state itself are viewed as
isolated entities, appropriately separated from one another. This perspective
reifies all three, particularly the individual and the institutional, which are
viewed as natural and ungovernable rather than socially constituted. The
paramount value under this conception is liberty, whether it is expressed as
mandating autonomy for the individual or a free market for the institutional,
and the state is the enemy. In consequence, this perspective limits the
development of understandings of the potential for the state to effectively
regulate institutions, modifying or structuring them in more responsive ways.
A restrained state is a state that can easily avoid assuming responsibility for
inequalities and unwarranted privilege because its position as the ultimate
societal authority, while recognized, is ideologically contained. It is important
to concede both that the state can be and has been abusive, overreaching, and
authoritative, and that avoiding this overreaching requires vigilance.
Nonetheless, advocating vigilance is not the same thing as urging abandonment
or retreat on the part of the state.
In contrast to the restrained state, the responsive state accepts responsibility
for its operation and also that of the societal institutions which it has helped
bring into existence. The responsive state views individuals and institutions as
intertwined, symbiotic, and interdependent with each other and also with the
state and its apparatus. Institutions are shaped through law and their operation
profoundly affects individual options, opportunities, and well-being and the
ability of the state to effectively govern. State responsiveness recognizes that
the intertwining of the individual with the institutional can be either generative
or destructive, warranting supervision and correction by the only entity capable
of doing so: the modern state. This state, in turn, should be understood as a
cluster of relationships, institutions, and agencies reflecting and shaping public
norms and values through law and policy. Those relationships include the
relationship between citizen and state, as well as between state and institutions.
In a responsive state individuals realize that they too comprise the state and
instead of standing outside of it they have a responsibility to see it is working
effectively. Perhaps we could call this relationship “democracy.”
The roadblocks to realizing a truly democratic and responsive state in the
United States are many. Responsiveness is under suspicion, particularly if it
costs money. Recently, the economic recession has served as an excuse and
provided political cover for arguments to further dismantle what was an already weak commitment to social welfare programs. However, the real
hurdles to the realization of the idea of a responsive state are ideological,
epitomized in the particularly distorted vision of what constitutes autonomy,
independence, and individual responsibility that has overtaken political
rhetoric and action in the United States.
To overcome the obsession with autonomy and individualism that has
impoverished American political discourse and resulted in the cynicism and
disaffection of so many citizens, it will be important to emphasize that the
basic foundational premise of the responsive state is inclusive, collective, and
radically democratic and egalitarian. The state, in this view, is constituted for
the “common benefit” and, thus, any privilege or favoritism resulting from
state action or concession must be justified in those terms. The focus should
be on the state’s responsibility for and relationship to those who are privileged,
as well as those who are disadvantaged. Structures that have served to
unequally allocate society’s resources to the benefit of the few must be
monitored and reformed. To do this, it will be necessary to ensure more
transparency in law and policymaking and to provide far greater opportunities
for public assessment of legislative and executive actions so that the idea of a
democratic correction for political impropriety is more than just an empty
promise in political science textbooks.
Initially, the common-benefit premise would have to be applied both as a
basis against which to assess the appropriateness of existing privilege in
society and as a means by which to analyze the generation of new forms of
privilege. This Article began by documenting the vast and growing inequality
in American society. The construction and valorization of the restrained state
has helped to facilitate that inequality, and its resultant privileging should be
assessed critically to determine whether policies that perpetuate the status quo
are justified. Politicians will tell us that this is an impossible task when what
they really mean is that it will place them in an uncomfortable position, particularly with those who are most privileged. The answer to their
concerns is to reiterate that the responsive state begins and ends with the
concept of political responsibility. This responsibility is placed on politicians
and state functionaries to ensure access to and opportunities within the
institutions that have been entrusted with generating and allocating wealth,
power, and position in a market society. Political responsibility precedes and
is an essential complement to the idea of personal responsibility, which
focuses only on individual autonomy and free-market ideals.
In understanding how we might conceive of a responsive state, it is
important to realize that just like the individual and the institutional, the state is vulnerable. This is true whether the state is perceived as restrained or as responsive. Powerful entrenched interests can hijack even the most egalitarian
impulse for their own purposes. Governmental structures and practices can
facilitate such distortions. As recent arguments in favor of corporate
subsidies and advantages for the wealthy have illustrated, assertions that
privileging is done for the common good are susceptible to manipulation. This is particularly true in a political system that is contentious, obfuscating, and renders legislators and executives ineffective by tolerating processes that are
prone to manipulation and distortion of facts and arguments rather than
conducive to problem solving and cooperative bipartisanship. The challenge
is how to structure state responsiveness in light of its vulnerabilities, namely
the possibility of capture and corruption, and the current tendency of the
political system to actually provide incentives for overreaching, repressive
tactics, and democracy-frustrating “hyper-partisanship.”
In Till v. Wheeler [2008] QDC 74 McGill DCJ considered a pseudolaw argument in which Till claimed to enjoy 'sovereign immunity' as a sovereign citizen.
The judgment states
[4] On 14 November 2007 a document by way of outline of argument on behalf of the appellant was filed in each matter. The two documents are identical, and purport to be a declaration by the appellant. The contents are essentially unintelligible, and do not constitute anything in the way of a coherent argument addressing any of the grounds in either notice of appeal, or advancing anything relevant to the question of whether either appeal should be allowed. He stated, for example: “I am a sovereign being living in a sovereign estate in the greater universe continuum. ... Sovereignty is not subject to law, it is the law, and its greatest claim to power is that IT and nothing else is the law. ...” The closest this comes to anything in the way of an intelligible legal argument is an assertion that the appellant is entitled to sovereign immunity.
Sovereign immunity
[5] At common law the position of a sovereign was clear. “It is clear law that the courts of this country will not implead a foreign sovereign,[1] that is, they will not by their process make him against his will a party to legal proceedings, whether the proceedings involve process against his person or seek to recover from him specific property or damages.” – Van Heyningen v Netherlands-Indies Government [1949] St R Qd 54 at 60. This comes from the notion that the authority of the courts derived from the sovereign who is not superior to a foreign sovereign, so that disputes between two sovereigns cannot be decided in the court of one of them. “For this purpose all sovereigns are equal. The independent sovereign of the smallest state stands on the same footing as the monarch of the greatest.” This extended to prosecutions of criminal offences in the ordinary courts
[6] The doctrine of sovereign immunity was codified in England by the State Immunity Act 1978. By that time, there had been a certain amount of development in the doctrine so far as it related to the capacity to bring civil actions against foreign governments or foreign states in the domestic courts, and the legislation was principally directed to those issues. Following this, in 1982 the Commonwealth Attorney-General referred to the Commonwealth Law Reform Commission the issue of sovereign or state immunity, and in 1984 the Law Reform Commission issued a report on “foreign state immunity” which included a draft of suitable legislation. The report was principally directed to the question of the extent to which activities of foreign states, particularly activities which were essentially of a commercial nature, should expose the states or bodies associated with the states to the ordinary jurisdiction of the courts.
[7] By the 1980s there was relatively little consideration given to the issue of personal immunity for individual sovereigns, but the question of heads of state was considered, and it was recommended at paragraph 163 that their position be best dealt with by equating their status for the purposes of domestic courts with heads of diplomatic missions. The position of diplomats had become well established by a series of international conventions, culminating in the Vienna convention on diplomatic relations, which was adopted in Australia by the Diplomatic Privileges and Immunities Act 1967, s 7(1). Article 31 of the convention provides for diplomatic agents, which includes heads of mission, immunity from domestic courts in relation to inter alia criminal matters.
[8] The Foreign States Immunities Act 1985, which was enacted following the report of the Commission, essentially adopted it, and provided in s 36 that a foreign head of state, which would include a foreign sovereign, would have the same immunity as a head of mission. Accordingly now, by statute, a foreign sovereign has immunity from the criminal courts in Australia.
[9] The difficulty facing the appellant in relation to this assertion, however, is the question of proof. In some circumstances the identity of a sovereign may be sufficiently notorious that proof will be unnecessary and the court will take judicial notice of the relevant fact. In other circumstances, at common law the court acted on a certificate from the relevant minister or department as to the recognition of the relevant sovereign by Australia. In Mighell (supra) the court acted on a certificate as to the status of the Sultan of Johore sent on behalf of the Secretary of State for the Colonies by an official of the Colonial Office. In Van Heyningen (supra) the court acted on a letter from the Acting Minister for External Affairs as to the status of the Dutch East Indies. This has been said to be the only procedure by which the question of whether a sovereign is a sovereign may be proved for the purposes of a proceeding in court.
[10] The 1985 Act also provides the appropriate mechanism for proof that a particular individual is a head of a foreign state for the purposes of the Act: by s 40, the Minister for Foreign Affairs may certify in writing who is or was the head of a foreign state for the purposes of the Act, and may delegate the power to so certify. By subsection (5), such a certificate is admissible and conclusive evidence on the point. Accordingly, the appropriate method of proof is to produce a certificate from the Minister or the Minister’s delegate. The appellant has provided no evidence from the Minister for Foreign Affairs or his department that he is a sovereign recognised by Australia. Although the Act makes the certificate conclusive, it does not expressly provide that this is the only method of proof, but it does not expressly authorise any other method of proof, and it seems to me that the common law position laid down by Lord Atkin would apply, at least in any case where the position was not so plain as to justify the taking of judicial notice.
[11] Even if this is not correct, and it would be possible to prove, by historical materials or other documents or evidence properly put before the court, that the appellant was a sovereign, there was no evidence in the present case to that effect put before the magistrate, nor any proper attempt to put any such evidence before me. A mere assertion by an individual or on behalf of an individual that he is sovereign is not conclusive, or indeed of any weight. The claim of sovereign immunity must be rejected.