Given that Meow-Ludo Disco Gamma Meow-Meow -
noted last year - is in the news again it was timely to read 'DIY Bio: Hacking Life in Biotech’s Backyard' by Lisa C. Ikemoto in (2017) 51
University of California Davis Law Review 539.
The peripatic Meow-Meow - recurrent political candidate, cyborg advocate and biohacking enthusiast - has unsurprisingly had his OPAL near-field transit card cancelled after he extracted the chip for subcutaneous insertion. He appears to consider that the resulting litigation - contesting a $200 fine in 2017 for riding the train without a valid ticket and reportedly planning to launch legal action against TfNSW for unlawfully cancelling his cards - will advance cyborg rights.
Australian law does not recognise 'cyborgs' as such and his action would appear to be readily addressed under the terms and conditions for use of his card.
In the Australian Capital Territory there is a prohibition under Regulation 49 of the
Road Transport (Public Passenger Services) Regulation 2002 (ACT) of traveling on an ACT government bus using a ticket that has been 'damaged or defaced in a material respect' or 'changed in a material particular', with ticket including a card with a chip or magnetic strip.
In NSW use of the OPAL travel card is governed by the
Passenger Transport (General) Regulation 2017 (NSW). The Cards 'are and remain' the property of TransportNSW, which may 'inspect, de-activate or take possession of an Opal Card or require its return at our discretion without notice at any time'.
Users are required to 'take proper care of the Opal Card, avoid damaging it, keep it flat and not bend or pierce it' and - saliently - 'not misuse, deface, alter, tamper with or deliberately damage or destroy the Opal Card'. Further, the user must not 'alter, remove or replace any notices (other than the activation sticker), trademarks or artwork on the Opal Card. Additionally, they must not'modify, adapt, translate, disassemble, decompile, reverse engineer, create derivative works of, copy or read, obtain or attempt to discover by any means, any (i) encrypted software or encrypted data contained on an Opal Card; or (ii) other software or data forming part of the Opal Ticketing System'.
Meow-Meow gained attention several years ago regarding 'biohacking' (centred on a DIY community DNA-modification lab) rather than 'bodyhacking'.
Ikemoto comments
DIY biologists set up home labs in garages, spare bedrooms, or use
community lab spaces. They play with plasmids, yeast, and tools like
CRISPR-cas9. Media stories feature glow-in-the-dark plants, beer, and
even puppies. DIY bio describes itself as a loosely formed community of
individualists, working separate and apart from institutional science. This
Essay challenges that claim, arguing that institutional science has fostered
DIY bio and that DIY bio has, thus far, tacitly conformed to institutional
science values and norms. Lack of a robust ethos leaves DIY bio ripe for
capture by biotech. Yet, this Essay suggests, DIY bio could serve as a
laboratory for reformulating a relationship between science and society
that is less about capital accumulation and more about knowledge creation
premised on participation and justice.
She goes on
Popular media depicts biohackers or Do-It-Yourself (“DIY”)
biologists as the ultimate science geeks. “DIY bio” refers to noninstitutional
science or science performed outside of professional
laboratories. DIY biologists set up home labs in garages, spare
bedrooms, and closets or use community lab spaces. The people
doing DIY bio range from the self-taught to PhDs. Instead of building
computers or creating apps, DIYers play with plasmids, jellyfish, yeast,
and polymerase chain reaction in genetic engineering experiments.
Media stories and DIY bio websites often feature glow-in-the-dark
plants, food, petri dish art, and even puppies.
DIY bio is an emerging set of activities. A range of players, with
varied ideologies, are shaping DIY bio’s trajectories. DIY bio’s
signature claim is that it exists apart from, and even in opposition to,
institutional science. This Essay challenges that claim. Whether all
DIY biologists know this or not, DIY bio serves the interests of
institutional science and is well-situated for capture by biotechnology.
Biotechnology refers not only to the life sciences-based industry, but
also to the neoliberal epistemology that values the use of applied
science to commercialize the transformation of life itself into
technology. DIY bio’s origin stories do reflect resistance to the highly structured and bureaucratic nature of institutional science. Yet these
accounts also indicate interest convergence between DIY bio and
institutional science. Accounts that forecast DIY bio’s future show DIY
bio conforming its practices to mainstream law, policy, and market
concerns. Thus far, DIY bio has not crafted its own account of the
relationship between science, society, and ethics, and is falling into a
science-as-usual practice that situates DIY bio in biotech’s backyard.
Part II sets out a descriptive account of biohacking, and DIY bio, in
particular. Part III identifies three overlapping explanations for DIY
bio. The first two, explicitly political accounts and nostalgic accounts,
are largely consistent with the DIY bio claim that DIY bio is different
and apart from institutional science. The third account borrows from
Frederick Jackson Turner’s frontier thesis and asserts that DIY bio
sustains an ideology of bio-individualism embedded in biotechnology.
Part IV reviews and critiques law and policy views of DIY bio and its
prospects. These views apply the frames and standards applicable to
biotech. Part V makes the case for biotech’s annexation of DIY bio.
Part V elaborates on DIY bio’s failure, so far, to re-define the
relationship between science and society, and suggests a few initial
critical points of engagement for doing so.
She suggests that
As yet, DIY bio has not expressed a commitment to ethical science
activity, nor developed a robust ethos. Perhaps, its tacit acceptance of
the risk-benefit framework means that its view of ethics aligns with
that of institutional science. That is, it conflates a risk-benefit
weighing with ethical standards or views ethics as a compliance
obligation.
The risk calculus is not devoid of ethical concerns. It maps onto a
standard ethical test used in institutional science. The test highlights
three criteria — safety, efficacy, and autonomy. That test derives
from the Belmont Report’s principlist framework, the FDA’s drug and
device approval standards, and neoliberalism’s effects on the life
sciences and autonomy. The Belmont Report states four principles —
autonomy, beneficence, non-maleficence, and distributive justice.
Autonomy’s application is informed consent. The non-maleficence
principle is addressed by weighing risk to human health against benefits. Benefits refer to efficacy or improvements to human health.
The FDA uses safety and efficacy as its criteria in the drug and device
testing requirements for market approval. Efficacy, like safety or
risk to human health, is narrowly defined. The FDA requires that the
product work, but does not require that it work well or better than
existing therapeutics. Market thinking has infiltrated these criteria.
Claims that individual choice should trump agency standards in
determining access to drugs have gained credence. This indicates
that traditional bioethics’ first principle, autonomy, may now be
understood as a form of free market individualism. In addition, the
pharmaceutical industry has leveraged that version of autonomy to
maximize the role of drugs in medical care, and the sale of particular
products. While big bio’s risk calculus is not the end-all and be-all
of ethics in institutional science, it is part of an impoverished ethical
framework.
In 2011, the North American and European DIYbio Congresses
issued Draft Codes of Ethics. The codes incorporate principles of open
science — open access, transparency, and education; and selfregulation
— safety (adopt safe practices), environment (respect the
environment), and peaceful purposes (biotechnology should only be
used for peaceful purposes). As discussed, the North American
Code has one more element — Tinkering. The Code elements are
general. As my characterization suggests, the Code elements, like the
Belmont Report principles, lend themselves to narrow or broad
readings. Read more generously, safety, environment, and peaceful
purposes might move DIY bio beyond the issue of forestalling
regulation to situating science as a tool for social justice. On the other
hand, open access could be read as a right to access, premised on free
market individualism. Tinkering invokes the individual, as the nostalgic accounts show. If DIY bio is first and foremost an
individualist vision of science, it stands little chance of evolving into a
new understanding of science.
The open science principles suggest that DIY bio’s ethos differs from
big bio’s, and that DIY bio is not bound by big bio’s norms. Yet, open
science goals do not translate to an ethics of science. Open science can
be used for different goals, including forms of commercial
distribution that are exploitative. In addition, the Code states the
elements as universal principles, which in itself is problematic.
Typically, dominant readings of so-called universal principles are used
to maintain boundaries, and identify the out-group as non-compliant.
It is very possible that the universal principles may be used to
undercut the inclusive goals that open science asserts.
My comments in the previous subparts suggest, without prescriptive
detail, the possibility of using DIY bio to redefine the possible
relationship between science and society. Contemporary accounts
indicate that DIY bio projects are typically small-scale and are
relatively unsophisticated. As such, DIY bio seems underpowered as
a platform for re-thinking the political economy of the life sciences.
What I suggest here is not that DIY biologists directly challenge or
redesign institutional science. Rather, DIY bio might provide an
opportunity to create, by deliberate experimentation, a set of practices
that are ethos-based and originate from critical social inquiry. The
most valorized explanatory accounts speak, in bits and pieces, of social
justice goals. Using these as a starting point, DIY bio might craft ways
of doing science that embed justice-based ethics into inquiry and
practice. Ethics, then, could become not a compliance checklist, but
constitutive of good science.
Ikemoto concludes
DIY bio is many things to many people. That is, undoubtedly, part
of its appeal. What is it not, however, is separate and apart from
institutional science. Its location in biotech’s backyard, without a
fence or substantive alternative vision of DIY bio’s role, makes it
vulnerable to annexation. In that scenario, DIY bio and its dream of a
new science by the people might disappear. This Essay maps the
relationships between DIY bio and institutional science. The mapping also critiques aspects of biotechnology that are inconsistent with DIY
bio’s stated goals of access and participatory knowledge formation. If
DIY bio takes those goals seriously, this Essay suggests that it move
beyond compliance-based thinking, and beyond experimentation
using plasmids and pipettes. Acknowledging that science is a social
practice, followed by scientific-social inquiry about how and why we
engage with plasmids and pipettes, and willingness to experiment with
new social methods of doing science, might move DIY bio out of
biotech’s backyard, and into society.