'Gender and the Analytical Jurisprudential Mind' (Oxford Legal Studies Research Paper No. 46/2015) by Leslie Green
asks
Why does contemporary jurisprudence have so little to say about law and gender? I think that is because gender is not relevant to theories of the nature of law. Joanne Conaghan disagrees. She says the methods of analytic philosophy screen out gender by abstracting concepts from social contexts, smuggling in hidden values, and ignoring empirical evidence. My own work on the law of marriage is said to exemplify this. But Conaghan is comprehensively mistaken in her diagnosis. She misunderstands analytic jurisprudence, misunderstands the relation between sex and gender, and misunderstands the role of social facts in legal philosophy. Feminist legal theory is made poorer if it accepts the caricature she offers. Legal scholars should be more open to the contributions of analytic philosophy to feminist inquiry.
Green writes
What can feminism contribute to the study of law?
A lot. It can help us understand what it is for women to
be disadvantaged in law, the varied ways that happens,
and the remedies that might be feasible. What can
feminism contribute to the study of jurisprudence? This
is trickier. Of course, if ‘jurisprudence means law
— for instance, case law or general principles of law
— then we already have our answer. But what if jurisprudence
means the philosophy of law and, in particular, the
philosophy of law in the analytic style familiar
throughout the Anglophone world and, now, in many
other places as well?
There is good feminist writing in the normative
branches of jurisprudence that overlap moral and
political philosophy. We know what (some) feminists
say about the importance of relationships in morality, or
about pornography and free speech, or about the
connection between domestic equality and political
justice. There is no harmony on such issues, but we do
have an idea of what a feminist position might look like.
When we turn to general questions about the nature of
law, however, the very idea of a feminist approach is
puzzling. What is a feminist line on whether law contains
power conferring rules? What should feminists think
about the identity of legal systems over time? What counts as a feminist view on the possibility of vicious
legal systems? With respect to such issues no feminist
positions come to mind. I think the explanation for that
is straightforward. A central feature of feminist theory is
attention to gender, and gender is not relevant to any of
these problems.
By ‘not relevant’ I mean that no position about
gender relations makes any answer to these questions
more or less plausible. Suppose you are wondering
whether, as Hans Kelsen thought, what appear to be
power conferring rules in the law are best seen as
fragments of duty imposing rules. No view about
gender — what constitutes it, what its social importance is,
how it shapes people’s lives — is going to tilt the answer in favour of or against Kelsen’s thesis. By way of
contrast, suppose you are wondering whether, as John
Rawls thought, the domain of justice is the ‘basic
structure’ of a society. Given what we know about the
gendered division of power and labour within families,
the plausibility of that thesis turns on whether and how
the idea of the ‘basic structure’ treats the family. So
gender is highly relevant to theories of justice. That is
why there are feminist theories of justice but no feminist
theories of legal rules. The same goes for most other
problems in general jurisprudence: there are no feminist
theories of the sources of law, no feminist theories of the
existence conditions for legal systems, no feminist
theories of the identity of legal systems, no feminist
theories of the normativity of law, and so on. We no
more expect to see feminist theories in general
jurisprudence then we expect to see feminist theories of
vagueness or feminist interpretations of quantum
mechanics. The reason jurisprudence says so little
about gender is that gender is not relevant there.
Or so it seems to me. But in a survey of issues
about law and gender, Joanne Conaghan offers a very
different diagnosis. She thinks that legal theorists
working in general jurisprudence do not say much
about gender because they fail to make room for it. Conaghan
holds gender to be pervasively relevant, not only to
law — no one denies that — but throughout legal
philosophy. Things seem otherwise only because men
have stacked the deck: ‘the concept of law (to invoke the
title of Hart’s famous work) has been endlessly
interrogated in terms which do not admit the relevance of
gender.’(6) Conaghan offers no direct argument in support of
that claim. She does not identify a single ‘interrogation’
of the concept of law that excludes gender where gender
is plausibly relevant.
Her case is diffuse and indirect. She sharply criticizes some of my own work in which she
detects an ethos that is, she claims, the sort of ethos that
conceals the relevance of gender to jurisprudence.
Now, since the work she criticizes is focused on conceptual
issues about sex, gender, and marriage, and since it is not
work in general jurisprudence, one might wonder how it
could serve as evidence for her charge. How could a
work treating gender not admit the relevance of gender?
How could a work about one local problem in special
jurisprudence — the nature of marriage in common law — reveal anything about the relevance of gender to the
concept of law? Conaghan’s answer is that it offers ‘a
rare glimpse into how sex/gender is conceived in the
analytical jurisprudential mind’. (169) She says that
glimpse reveals the general ‘methodological limitations
which characterize [such] jurisprudential analysis,’
namely:
the abstraction of legal concepts from the
framework in which they operate and the tendency
to treat them as having a fairly fixed content over
time and space; the unarticulated normative
prioritization of some features... over others...,
evidencing the presence of evaluative choices which
problematize any claim to be rendering a
descriptive or value neutral account; the overlooking, or at least unexplained disregard, of
contra indicative evidence.... (176)
If we would free legal philosophy from this sort of
mindset exhibited in my work and allow for the
historicity of concepts, if we would prioritize the right
features of law and acknowledge we are doing that, if we
would play closer attention to empirical evidence, we
would find that gender is important to jurisprudence in
ways that the ‘analytical jurisprudential mind’ cannot
begin to acknowledge. Gender is absent from general
jurisprudence, on Conaghan’s view, not because it is
irrelevant to it, but because the methods of analytic
philosophy screen it out.
If her diagnosis were correct, then to say that
analytical jurisprudence has ‘methodological limitations
would be an understatement. It would be a failure: (1)
To suppose that legal concepts are unchanging flies in the
face of the obvious; the law changes and so do some legal concepts. (2) To think we can describe anything without
prioritizing some of its features is to misunderstand the
nature of description. (3) To overlook or disregard
relevant evidence is incompetence or dishonesty. If that
is the mess analytical jurisprudence makes of things, I
think we would be lucky if its discussions of sex and
gender were, as Conaghan thinks, ‘rare’. Unsurprisingly, perhaps, I do not accept that I
have blundered in these ways and I shall explain why
not. One might doubt whether self defence could be enough to get the whole ‘analytical jurisprudential mind’
off the hook. Perhaps I am not prone to these vices but
everyone else is: maybe I escaped a bad upbringing. As
we shall see, however, Conaghan’s errors are of a general kind, not only false readings and misattributions,
but misunderstandings of analytic jurisprudence. Were
they to take hold they would be damaging to the
development of feminist legal theory.