'Authoritarian Liberalism: From
Schmitt via Ordoliberalism
to the Euro' by Werner Bonefeld in (2017) 43(4-5)
Critical Sociology 747 examines
the market liberal veracity of Hayek’s view that a dictatorship may
be more liberal in its policies than an unlimited democratic assembly. Hayek’s warning about the
potentially illiberal character of democratic government is key to the German ordoliberal thinking
that emerged in the context of the crisis of the Weimar Republic. The ordoliberal thinkers
were keenly aware of Schmitt’s political theology and argued with him that the state is the
predominant power in the relationship between market and state, conceiving of this relationship
as free economy and strong state. They maintained that the establishment of social order is the
precondition of free economy; law does not apply to disorder and does not create order. The
liberal state is the ‘concentrated force’ of that order. The contribution argues that ordoliberalism
is best characterized as an authoritarian liberalism and assesses its contemporary veracity in
relation to the European Union.
Bonefeld states
The program of liberalism ... summed up in a single word, should read ‘property’, that is,
private property in the means of production ... All other demands of liberalism derive from this
basic demand. (Von Mises, 1985: 137)
It cannot be denied that Fascism and similar movements aiming at the establishment of
dictatorships are full of the best intentions and that their intervention has, for the moment,
saved European civilization. (Von Mises, 1985: 51)
...
The term ‘authoritarian liberalism’ was coined by the German Jurist Hermann Heller in a 1933
publication about the rightist Von Papen government of 1932. His account explored Carl Schmitt’s
‘Strong State and Sound Economy’ (1998) as the theoretical manifestation of the authoritarian turn
of liberal thought. Heller characterized the turn towards authoritarianism as a demotion of democratic government ‘in favour of the dictatorial authority of the state’ (Heller, 2015: 296).
Schmitt’s stance was by and large shared by the founding thinkers of German ordoliberalism. They too identified the democratic character of the Weimar Republic as the root cause of the crisis of Weimar,
arguing that mass democracy is tyrannical in its consequences.
In the context of Weimar, the authoritarian reassertion of the state was thus not only meant to
overcome the ‘lamentable weakness’ (Friedrich, 1955: 512) of the liberal state. It was also meant
to reorder the socio-economic relations to achieve free economy. Authoritarian liberalism conceives of the state as ‘market police’ (Rüstow, 1942). According to Heller (2015) it posits the state
in its pure liberal form as the organized force and concentrated power of the system of liberty,
enforcing market freedom and sustaining depoliticized socio-economic relations. Depoliticization
is an eminently political practice. To Schmitt and the ordoliberals ‘the Leviathan was and had to be
there first’ (Streek, 2015: 363); and rightly so: by its own logic, and as Adam Smith had already
argued, free economy descends into ‘bloodshed and disorder’ (Smith, 1976: 340) unless the state
civilizes its conduct by means of law, police, and fabrication of the moral sentiments of the system
of private property. The freedom to compete presupposes ‘market police with strong state authority’ (Rüstow, 1942: 289) to sustain it. The strength of the state as market police depends on its
independence from society. Its capacity to neutralize democracy and civilize the conduct of a free
labour economy depends on the state as the independent and concentrated power of society.
In the late 1920s/early 1930s, the critique of mass democracy was part of the rightist reaction to
the Weimar Republic. In the 1950s, it became part of the ‘anti-totalitarian’ idea that mass democ-
racy leads to unfreedom, and that for the sake of an open society democracy needed to be fettered.
As Willgerodt and Peacock (1989: 6) put it, ‘those who rely on the rules for liberal decisions,
irrespective of the results of these decisions, must answer the question: how can it be guaranteed
that these decisions will not destroy the liberal rules?’. In this perspective, freedom needs to be
protected against the enemies of freedom even if they move formally within the legal bounds of a
free society and secure parliamentary majorities by free elections. That is, ‘trust in freedom must
be accompanied by a distrust of forces that abolish freedom or interfere with it’ (Lenel, 1989: 21).
Surveillance is the condition of trust. Recognition of the enemies of freedom depends on the certainty of indivisible socio-economic values and political norms that recognize free economy as a
‘universal form of existence’ (Eucken, 2004: 321).
There can be no doubt. Relativism has no
values to defend. It succumbs, they say, to ‘trouble makers’ (Röpke, 2009: 50). In this remarkable
manner, the rightist denunciation of Weimar democracy established itself as a militant defence of
post-war democracy. ‘Militant democracy’ rejects liberality as an open invitation to the enemy
within. Instead it demands the curtailment of democracy ostensibly in order to protect it against
attack and communist overthrow.
In the 1970s the authoritarian liberal critique of democracy came to the fore again in the context
of the then economic crisis. The debate focused by and large on Britain. It argued that the crisis had
been brought about by an excess of democracy that had let to an overloaded interventionist state,
which had stifled the economy with crisis-ridden consequences. Its crisis-diagnosis entailed the
prescription for resolving the crisis. The economy had to be set free by rolling back the state and
by curtailing the democratic excess. Its stance formed the theoretical foundation of the incoming
Thatcher government in 1979.
However, in Europe, the most sustained effort in neutralizing mass democracy occurred in the form of European monetary union, which created the world’s only state-less currency. The government of the Euro is to all intents and purposes entirely removed from the
territorially regimented democratic sovereigns. It sets in place a market liberal framework for the
conduct of policy in the federated and democratically constituted member states.
The paper lays out the argument that capitalist political economy entails the liberal state as
market police. This conception of the state excludes the idea of mass democracy as the constitutive
basis of the liberal rule of law. The next section introduces Schmitt’s authoritarian stance and
examines the ordoliberal critique of mass democracy. The following section presents the neoliberal
account of a crisis of democracy in the 1970s. The conclusion summarizes the argument with
reference to the elements of authoritarian liberalism in the governance of the Euro. I hold that the
European monetary union amounts to a system of imposed liberty, which strengthens the liberal
character of the member states. It also tends to nationalize the critique of ‘liberty’ in the form of
powerful neo-fascist political movements and parties, including populist nationalist rejection fed
by impotent rage and pitiful delusions about ‘land and sea’, as in the case of Brexit.